
Publication details
Publisher: Springer
Place: Berlin
Year: 2001
Pages: 1-63
Series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
ISBN (Hardback): 9789048157099
Full citation:
, "Reference, (in)commensurability and meanings", in: Incommensurability and related matters, Berlin, Springer, 2001


Reference, (in)commensurability and meanings
pp. 1-63
in: Howard Sankey (ed), Incommensurability and related matters, Berlin, Springer, 2001Abstract
Received conceptions of the meanings of scientific terms assign to meanings an essentially benign methodological role: the meaning of a term consists of principles or inference rules which are, always or for the most part, (approximately) true or reliable. In fact, many scientific terms have meanings which are malignant: which are mainly false or misleading and which detract from, rather than contribute to, scientific progress. Kuhn's conception of incommensurability can be fruitfully extended to take account of malignant meanings. Malignant meanings are especially implicated in cases, like that of human sociobiology, in which the influence of social ideology on scientific practice is especially profound.
Publication details
Publisher: Springer
Place: Berlin
Year: 2001
Pages: 1-63
Series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
ISBN (Hardback): 9789048157099
Full citation:
, "Reference, (in)commensurability and meanings", in: Incommensurability and related matters, Berlin, Springer, 2001